"The problem with socialism is that eventually you run out of other people's money."
--Margaret Thatcher
It would seem, then, that a government which could separate these two functions (deciding what is right and deciding what is fair) might have a chance to create a society which could avoid the transcendent and immanent extremes of the past. It is our contention that this is what the Fathers of the new American nation accomplished in establishing an independent judiciary charged with interpreting the Constitution.
"The problem with socialism is that eventually you run out of other people's money."
--Margaret Thatcher
Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances.
We see the First Amendment of the Constitution as the bedrock of our rights, protecting our freedom of speech and religion. As we have analyzed already, the primary role that the Bill of Rights plays in constitutional jurisprudence today is the protection of minority rights against repressive majorities. But the Founding generation was not looking for the protection of minorities. They had just suffered at the hands of British imperialism and militarism, and they sought protection against repressive central government.
The structure of the First Amendment sounds in majoritarianism, localism and federalism. One need look no further than the language of the amendment to see evidence of this truth: "Congress shall make no law..." Amar elaborates:
The body that is restrained is no a hostile majority of people, but rather Congress; and the earlier two amendments remind us that congressional may in fact have "aristocratical" and self-interested views in opposition to views held by a majority of the people. (p. 21)
Because of Congress' distance from local constituencies and the large number of constituencies represented by each congressman, the general concern was that Congress would "be less likely to reflect majority will." The courts were not expected to be the main arbiters of First Amendment rights either. Rather elections and states were expected to fill that role, as evidenced in the successful rallying against the Alien and Sedition Acts and the elections of 1800 which turned control of Congress over to Jefferson’s Republican Party.
Local juries also played a part in enforcing the freedoms of expression guaranteed by the First Amendment:
The common-law rule against “prior restraint” – courts could not enjoin a publisher from printing offensive material but could entertain civil and criminal prosecutions for libel and sedition afterward – had bite largely because of the structural differences between the two proceedings. The former could occur in equity courts, presided over by permanent government officials on the government payroll (chancellors), but the latter required the intervention of ordinary citizens (jurors) free to vote for the publisher without fear of reprisal. (p. 23)
Many publishers invoked the First Amendment at their jury trials for libel and sedition prosecutions under the Alien and Sedition Acts. The Federalists insisted that the right to free speech was not absolute, but in the English tradition, free speech rights grew up out of Parliament. In Article 1, Section 6 of the original Constitution, congressmen were shielded from various reprisals “for any Speech or Debate in either House.” Absolute freedom to speak one’s mind in the constitutionally-recognized legislature was a foundational principle in a society of parliamentary sovereignty. So in a society where the People were sovereign (America), why should the People as citizens not have absolute freedom to speak? No court ever declared the Alien and Sedition Acts unconstitutional, but several juries refused to find publishers guilty under the Acts because of the First Amendment. After the Federalists lost control of Congress in the elections of 1800, the Acts were allowed to expire, free-speech rights defended through the work, jealousies and vigilance of the People, rather than by the hand of government.
The Civil War and Fourteenth Amendment shifted this bias toward the insulated federal judiciary as it is unpopular, minority speech that is prosecuted in the courts. Rather than trusting popular opinion and the sentiment of that body of local citizens, defendants seek the protection of speech from judges who are free from popular political pressures. We will look at the Fourteenth Amendment in more detail when we examine what Amar has to say about its provisions, but for now it is enough to say that the First Amendment’s protections of free speech and expression are incorporated against the States through the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process clause (though incorporation really should be accomplished through the Privileges and Immunities clause, but again, we will discuss this in the appropriate place).
This progression should not surprise us, but the focus on individual and minority rights bleach out the rich tapestry of the popular-sovereignty logic and the roles of elections, states and local juries in protecting and building up the freedoms we all enjoy under our First Amendment.
imported from Wordpress. Original post date 5/21/2010
In the latest chapter of this odd project of saving religion by emptying it of its content, Justice Anthony Kennedy, writing for a plurality in Salazar v. Buono, ordered a district court to reconsider a ruling that Congress had impermissibly promoted religion by devising a plan designed to prevent the removal of a cross standing in the Mojave National Preserve. The cross had originally been erected in 1934 by the Veterans of Foreign Wars to commemorate American soldiers who had died in World War I. In 2002, Frank Buono, a retired Park Service employee, filed suit alleging a violation of the Establishment Clause and “sought an injunction requiring the government to remove the cross.
...
Notice what this paroxysm of patriotism had done: it has taken the Christianity out of the cross and turned it into an all-purpose means of marking secular achievements. (According to this reasoning the cross should mark the winning of championships in professional sports.) It is one of the ironies of the sequence of cases dealing with religious symbols on public land that those who argue for their lawful presence must first deny them the significance that provokes the desire to put them there in the first place.
It has become a formula: if you want to secure a role for religious symbols in the public sphere, you must de-religionize them, either by claiming for them a non-religious meaning as Kennedy does here, or, in the case of multiple symbols in a park or in front of a courthouse, by declaring that the fact of many of them means that no one of them is to be taken seriously; they don’t stand for anything sectarian; they stand for diversity. So you save the symbols by leeching the life out of them. The operation is successful, but the patient is dead.
My distaste for Kennedy’s opinion has nothing to do with its result. In general, and for the record, I have no problem with the state accommodating religious symbols and I am not bothered by the thought of a cross standing in a remote part of the Mojave desert even if the land it stands on is owned by the government. I do have a problem with reasoning that is patently dishonest and protests too much about its own motives and the motives of those it defends. But that is what the religion clause drives you to when in one of its clauses — the free exercise clause — it singles out religion for special positive treatment, and in the other clause — the Establishment Clause — it places a warning label (watch out for this stuff; it’s trouble) on religion. It’s no wonder that the justices who try to deal with this schizophrenia tie themselves in knots and produce opinions that are as unedifying as they are disingenuous.
As I have said, both of these clauses in the First Amendment ensure religious liberty, but in different ways. The Establishment Clause keeps government from indirectly hurting your religion by helping somebody else’s religion and Free Exercise keeps government from harming your religion directly. Even though these provisions are complementary, sometimes—when taken to their logical conclusion—they rub up against the other clause.
This tension between the two clauses is good. If one assiduously enforces the Establishment Clause and forgets about free exercise, an environment of hostility to religion can result. However, if one concentrates only on the Free Exercise Clause and forgets about no establishment, the logical outcome can be a theocracy or something close to it. In either case, religious liberty would be diminished.
In short, it is important that we understand that government should accommodate religion, without advancing it; protect religion, without privileging it; sometimes lift burdens on the exercise of religion without extending religion an impermissible benefit.
Although U.S. constitutional law has come up with elaborate typologies to help us sort through this dilemma (mandatory, permissible and impermissible exemptions), I like to employ a common sense exercise. Every time we say “no” to government activity to uphold the Establishment Clause, we should find a way to say “yes” to its Free Exercise counterpart. This allows us always to try to find a “win-win” solution.
Thomas Friedman has a valid point in his latest article No Fooling Mother Nature.
There is only one meaningful response to the horrific oil spill in the Gulf of Mexico and that is for America to stop messing around when it comes to designing its energy and environmental future.
We do need to stop messing around, but I differ with him on exactly how we are currently messing around and what we need to do to stop messing around. He thinks more government regulation and taxation is the answer to change behavior and to push the markets toward green technology. Rather than Yet Another energy bill from Congress loaded with taxation, regulation, and tax breaks that skew the market, Congress should pass an energy bill that removes tax breaks for the oil industry and keeps only regulation that guards against large-scale disasters (rather than, for example, worrying about caribou in ANWR or fish in California).
We will eventually get off oil (we will run out or some other fuel source will become more economical), but without perverse government policies in place, the market can drive what technologies can be introduced and when. The past ten years should have proven definitively the absolute inability of government bureaucrats to competently orchestrate big systems with lots of moving parts.
Article the first.... After the first enumeration required by the first Article of the Constitution, there shall be one Representative for every thirty thousand, until the number shall amount to one hundred, after which, the proportion shall be regulated by Congress, that there shall be not less that one hundred Representatives, not less that one Representative for every forty thousand persons, until the number of Representatives shall amount to two hundred, after which the proportion shall be so regulated by Congress, that there shall not be less than two hundred Representatives, not more than one Representative for every fifty thousand persons.
Probably the deepest Anti-Federalist objection to the Constitution was that the document took the skimming principle too far: Congress was too small, too rich, too "refined." Indeed, this structural concern underlay most of the Anti-Federalists' other arguments. Because the legislature was so small, the Anti-Federalists feared that only great men with reputations spanning wide geographic areas could secure election. [Amar 10-11]
It is natural for a republic to have only a small territory; otherwise it cannot long subsist. In an extensive republic there are men of large fortunes, and consequently of less moderation; there are trusts too considerable to be placed in any single subject; he has interests of his own; he soon begins to think that he may be happy and glorious, by oppressing his fellow-citizens; and that he may raise himself to grandeur on the ruins of his country.
In an extensive republic the public good is sacrificed to a thousand private views; it is subordinate to exceptions, and depends on accidents. In a small one, the interest of the public is more obvious, better understood, and more within the reach of every citizen; abuses have less extent, and, of course, are less protected. [Montesquieu, Spirit of Laws, Book 8, Ch. 16]
It must be confessed that in this, as in most other cases, there is a mean, on both sides of which inconveniences will be found to lie. By enlarging too much the number of electors, you render the representatives too little acquainted with all their local circumstances and lesser interests; as by reducing it too much, you render him unduly attached to these, and too little fit to comprehend and pursue great and national objects.
Proponents for such repeal argue for the original intent of the election of U.S. senators by state legislatures that it would better serve to protect the reserved powers of the states from encroachment by the central government, and that state legislators would bring more expertise to the selection process.
Unfortunately, that never worked as it was designed. What actually happened was that special interests, such as banking, railroads, oil, and steel, found that they could buy tU.S. senators for a lot less through state legislators than through direct popular election.
Most state legislatures had no strong desire to protect their citizens from the central government. They were more interested in getting federal money. Accepting large donations in exchange for voting for the U.S. Senate candidate of choice of the donor was a matter of almost all upside and little downside.
There is a reason why by 1912 so many state legislatures were holding popular referenda to nominate U.S. senators and then just rubber-stamping the popular choice.
Members of the United States Senate, and houses of state legislatures whose members represent political subdivisions not based on population, shall be selected by a multi-stage nominating process that first randomly selects precinct panels of twenty-four, who then elect a person from each precinct, from among whom are randomly selected twenty-four persons for the next higher jurisdiction or district, and thus by alternating random selection and election to the next level, when they reach the top level, the number of randomly selected candidates shall be five, who shall be the nominees on the ballot for the final election by general voters, except that general voters may write-in other persons. Voters may vote for more than one nominee, using the method of approval voting. There must also be an alternative of "none of the above". The nominee receiving the most votes shall be declared elected, unless "none of the above" wins, in which case the position shall remain vacant.
"Voters may vote for more than one nominee, using the method of approval voting."
If you really read the fairy-tales, you will observe that one idea runs from one end of them to the other—the idea that peace and happiness can only exist on some condition. This idea, which is the core of ethics, is the core of the nursery-tales. The whole happiness of fairyland hangs upon a thread, upon one thread. Cinderella may have a dress woven on supernatural looms and blazing with unearthly brilliance; but she must be back when the clock strikes twelve. The king may invite fairies to the christening, but he must invite all the fairies or frightful results will follow. Bluebeard's wife may open all doors but one. A promise is broken to a cat, and the whole world goes wrong. A promise is broken to a yellow dwarf, and the whole world goes wrong. A girl may be the bride of the God of Love himself if she never tries to see him; she sees him, and he vanishes away. A girl is given a box on condition she does not open it; she opens it, and all the evils of this world rush out at her. A man and woman are put in a garden on condition that they do not eat one fruit: they eat it, and lose their joy in all the fruits of the earth.
--G.K. Chesterton, "All Things Considered"
There is a series of little articles that G.K. Chesterton wrote bundled in the book All Things Considered. In the article "Patriotism and Sport," Chesterton writes:
Chesterton often turns conventional wisdom on its head, and since today's conventional wisdom is typically only the wisdom of his day stretched out and taken to its logical (and oft times illogical) extremes, many of his insights are as insightful today as they were in his own time. It is fashionable today to bemoan the state of America - her politics, her job market, her "lost" liberties, her social inequality, her international reputation, her antiquated institutions, her professionalization of many aspects of society... the list can go on and on. In some ways, we are right to worry about these things, as constant evaluation of where you are helps with the mid-course corrections needed to get to where you are going. I think that, however, we sometimes lose sight of the winding road's long course for fear of the numerous potholes we are swerving to avoid. The state of the United States now looks a lot like Rome in its decline, they say.But the real historic strength of England, physical and moral, has never had anything to do with this athletic specialism; it has been rather hindered by it. Somebody said that the Battle of Waterloo was won on Eton playing-fields. It was a particularly unfortunate remark, for the English contribution to the victory of Waterloo depended very much more than is common in victories upon the steadiness of the rank and file in an almost desperate situation. The Battle of Waterloo was won by the stubbornness of the common soldier—that is to say, it was won by the man who had never been to Eton. It was absurd to say that Waterloo was won on Eton cricket-fields. But it might have been fairly said that Waterloo was won on the village green, where clumsy boys played a very clumsy cricket. In a word, it was the average of the nation that was strong, and athletic glories do not indicate much about the average of a nation. Waterloo was not won by good cricket-players. But Waterloo was won by bad cricket-players, by a mass of men who had some minimum of athletic instincts and habits.
For all I know, we might look a lot like Rome in decline. I wouldn't know; I never lived in Rome. But I have studied this country and lived with her people for almost four decades, and that experience does give me the ability to say a few things about the U.S. Americans are a hard-working, innovative people who are very engaged in their families and communities. States and the nation as a whole produce bright, energetic leaders and thinkers who work to make things better for the country. We know how to compromise to avoid extremes, and we have a uniquely American way of doing things. We've been stumbling about for over two hundred years, but somehow we continue to find a way to stumble forward.
By all rights, the United States should not be a great power - we are loosely organized and governed, we are not good at managing complex systems, we have multiple-layers of power and thousands of points of responsibility. Yet we have constantly risen to meet challenges that threaten us. Time and again, we have shown that we can come together and beat the odds. We reinvent ourselves and, somehow, end up on top - or at least among the leaders.
I attribute this to the grit of the average American. We live passionately and love our families, communities, and country, yet we fight constantly - among ourselves with words and too easily against other peoples with weapons. We believe in who we are, yet we find ways to treat each other as humans to tolerate dissent and conversation. We hate government, yet we continue to find creative ways to channel it to solve societal ills even as we turn around again to constrain and shackle it. We are full of paradox, yet we are guided by an everyday plain-ness, and average-ness, that is really not all that plain or average.
The United States is not perfect as a country. But Americans as a people are not Romans, and history does not repeat itself. At least not in the way most of the Talking Heads mean.
So what happens when cultural expectations for ethical behavior are largely removed? What happens when a number of leading voices say that the ideas of "right" and "wrong" are meaningless or even destructive? What happens when prevailing voices say that morality is solely a private matter? In terms of our inner struggles, it means that the person can no longer enlist the help of the culture in taming his lower instincts. It means that the person develops a less-controlled animal side than would have developed otherwise. It leads to a stunted conscience.
On request from the Congress, the president shall appear once every two weeks on the floor of Congress to receive and respond to questions from the members of Congress during periods of regular legislative session. The president shall alternate chambers, appearing on the Senate floor to receive questions from members of the Senate, then appearing two weeks later on the House of Representatives floor to receive questions from the members of the House of Representatives. Each appearance shall be for a minimum of thirty minutes and a maximum of one hour, and the majority and minority party of that chamber of the legislature each shall receive one-half of the question time.
In the United States, leaders in the House of Representatives have done an effective job in getting their members to think in group, not person-to-person, terms. Members usually vote as party blocs. Individuals have very little power. That’s why representatives are often subtle and smart as individuals, but crude and partisan as a collective. The social psychology of the House is a clan psychology, not an interpersonal psychology.
The Senate, on the other hand, has historically been home to more person-to-person thinking. This is because the Senate is smaller and because of Senate rules. Until recently, the Senate leaders couldn’t just ram things through on party-line votes. Because a simple majority did not rule, and because one senator had the ability to bring the whole body to a halt, senators had an incentive, every day, to develop alliances and relationships with people in the other party.
For decades, individual senators have resisted their leaders’ attempts to run the Senate like the House and destroy these relationships and these humane customs. A few years ago, when Republican leaders tried to pass judicial nominations on party-line votes, rank-and-file members like Barack Obama, Joe Biden and Hillary Clinton spoke out forcefully against rule by simple majority.
But power trumps principle. In nearly every arena of political life, group relationships have replaced person-to-person relationships. The tempo of the Senate is now set by partisan lunches every Tuesday, whereas the body almost never meets for conversation as a whole. The Senate is now in the process of using reconciliation — rule by simple majority — to try to pass health care.
Reconciliation has been used with increasing frequency. That was bad enough. But at least for the Bush tax cuts or the prescription drug bill, there was significant bipartisan support. Now we have pure reconciliation mixed with pure partisanship.